Grammar
Tenses
Present
Present Simple
Present Continuous
Present Perfect
Present Perfect Continuous
Past
Past Continuous
Past Perfect
Past Perfect Continuous
Past Simple
Future
Future Simple
Future Continuous
Future Perfect
Future Perfect Continuous
Passive and Active
Parts Of Speech
Nouns
Countable and uncountable nouns
Verbal nouns
Singular and Plural nouns
Proper nouns
Nouns gender
Nouns definition
Concrete nouns
Abstract nouns
Common nouns
Collective nouns
Definition Of Nouns
Verbs
Stative and dynamic verbs
Finite and nonfinite verbs
To be verbs
Transitive and intransitive verbs
Auxiliary verbs
Modal verbs
Regular and irregular verbs
Action verbs
Adverbs
Relative adverbs
Interrogative adverbs
Adverbs of time
Adverbs of place
Adverbs of reason
Adverbs of quantity
Adverbs of manner
Adverbs of frequency
Adverbs of affirmation
Adjectives
Quantitative adjective
Proper adjective
Possessive adjective
Numeral adjective
Interrogative adjective
Distributive adjective
Descriptive adjective
Demonstrative adjective
Pronouns
Subject pronoun
Relative pronoun
Reflexive pronoun
Reciprocal pronoun
Possessive pronoun
Personal pronoun
Interrogative pronoun
Indefinite pronoun
Emphatic pronoun
Distributive pronoun
Demonstrative pronoun
Pre Position
Preposition by function
Time preposition
Reason preposition
Possession preposition
Place preposition
Phrases preposition
Origin preposition
Measure preposition
Direction preposition
Contrast preposition
Agent preposition
Preposition by construction
Simple preposition
Phrase preposition
Double preposition
Compound preposition
Conjunctions
Subordinating conjunction
Correlative conjunction
Coordinating conjunction
Conjunctive adverbs
Interjections
Express calling interjection
Grammar Rules
Preference
Requests and offers
wishes
Be used to
Some and any
Could have done
Describing people
Giving advices
Possession
Comparative and superlative
Giving Reason
Making Suggestions
Apologizing
Forming questions
Since and for
Directions
Obligation
Adverbials
invitation
Articles
Imaginary condition
Zero conditional
First conditional
Second conditional
Third conditional
Reported speech
Linguistics
Phonetics
Phonology
Semantics
Pragmatics
Linguistics fields
Syntax
Morphology
Semantics
pragmatics
History
Writing
Grammar
Phonetics and Phonology
Reading Comprehension
Elementary
Intermediate
Advanced
Variable telicity in degree achievements - Telicity and vagueness
المؤلف:
CHRISTOPHER KENNEDY AND BETH LEVIN
المصدر:
Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse
الجزء والصفحة:
P157-C7
2025-04-21
87
Variable telicity in degree achievements - Telicity and vagueness
Vendler (1957) distinguishes atelic predicates (activities) like run from telic predicates (accomplishments) like run a mile on the basis of whether they entail of an event that a “set terminal point” has been reached. Most studies of variable telicity focus on contrasts like run for/??in four minutes vs. run a mile in/??for four minutes, because they show that compositional interactions between a verb and its argument(s) can affect the telicity of the predicate (Verkuyl 1972; Mourelatos 1978; Bach 1986; Krifka 1989). Degree achievements (DAs) present a special challenge, however, because they may have variable telicity independently of the properties of their arguments, as first observed by Dowty (1979). Consider for example the uses of cool in (1a–b).1
The acceptability of the in-PP in (1a) shows that cool can be telic, and indeed this sentence is true of an event only if it leads to an endstate in which the affected participant has come to be cool. However, the acceptable for-PP in (1b) shows that cool can also be atelic, and this example implies neither that the endstate associated with (1a) (“coolness”) has been reached, nor that a sequence of distinct change of state eventualities has taken place (as in iterated achievements like Kim discovered crabgrass in the yard for six weeks; see Dowty 1979). Similarly, whether or not the progressive form in (2a) entails the perfect in (2b) depends on whether we understand cool in (2a) only as implying that the temperature of the soup is getting lower (atelic; (2b) entailed), or as implying that the temperature of the soup is moving towards an understood endstate of being cool (telic; (2b) not entailed).
The challenge then is to identify the factors which lead to variable telicity in DAs. Building on ideas in Dowty (1979), Abusch (1986) proposes that the variable telicity of DAs (her “vague inchoatives”) is parasitic on a different kind of variability in the meanings of the expressions that describe the endstates such verbs imply (in their telic uses). Following Dowty, Abusch takes the lexical meaning of an inchoative verb to be as in (3a), where P is a property of individuals, with truth conditions as in (3b).2
Abusch observes that what is special about DAs like cool is that P corresponds to a vague predicate: what counts as cool is a matter of context, and there will typically be some things for which it is impossible to say whether they are cool or not (so-called “borderline cases”). Building on the analyses of vague predicates in Kamp (1975) and Klein (1980) (see also McConnell-Ginet 1973 and Fine 1975), Abusch analyzes adjectival cool as a function cool from contexts to properties of individuals, and proposes that the variability of verbal cool depends on whether the contextual argument of cool is fixed to the context of utterance, as in (4a), or is bound by an existential quantifier, as in (4b).
In (4a), cool(c u) is the property of being cool in the context of utterance. This is the meaning of the positive (unmarked) form of the adjective, which is true of objects that are at least as cool as some contextual “standard” of temperature. (The standard can vary both on properties of the object and on properties of the context: cool lemonade is normally cooler than cool coffee, and coffee that counts as cool relative to one’s desire to drink it in the morning with a bagel is typically warmer than coffee that counts as cool relative to one’s desire to pour it over ice without turning the whole thing into a watery mess.) Saturation of the individual argument x derives a property that is true of an event just in case x is not as cool as the contextual standard at the beginning of the event, and is at least as cool as the standard at the end of the event; the requirement that this transition be made renders the predicate telic.
In (4b), the context variable is existentially bound, which means that the predicate is true of an event just in case there is some context such that x is not cool relative to that context at the beginning of the event and is cool relative to the context at the end of the event, that is, that x has a coolness that is below the standard of comparison for that context at the beginning of the event, and above it at the end. But this merely requires an increase in coolness (which amounts to a decrease in temperature, since cool is a “polar negative” adjective; see Seuren 1978; Bierwisch 1989; Kennedy 2001), and there is no entailment that a particular endstate is reached. Assuming an arbitrary number of contextual interpretations of vague predicates, differing only in where along a gradable continuum they draw the line between the things they are true and false of, (4b) is true of any subevent of an event that it is true of. In other words, it has the “subinterval property,” and so is atelic (Bennett and Partee 1982).
Abusch’s analysis predicts that DAs in general should behave like cool, having either telic or atelic interpretations depending on whether the adjectival root is analyzed in a “positive” sense as in (4a) or a “comparative” sense as in (4b).3 One potential problem for this analysis comes from the fact that many DAs have default telic interpretations. Such verbs have atelic uses, but in the absence of explicit morphosyntactic or contextual information forcing such interpretations, they are treated as telic. This is illustrated by the examples in (5).
As observed by Kearns (2007), the most natural interpretations of examples like these are ones in which the affected objects reach the endstate named by the positive form of the adjective, as illustrated by the oddity of the completions in parentheses. These completions do not result in true contradictions, showing that the telic interpretation is not obligatory, but they do result in degraded acceptability.4 In particular, they have the feel of “garden path effects,” suggesting that the verbs in (5) have default telic positive interpretations, and the completions require reanalysis to the atelic, comparative ones. A potential explanation for this default is a pragmatic one: since the telic interpretation entails the atelic one, it is more informative and therefore stronger. In the absence of information to the contrary – which could in principle be implicit (contextual), compositional (such as modification that is consistent only with atelicity), or even lexical (word-based defaults) – the strongest meaning should be preferred, resulting in a preference for telic interpretations (cf. Dalrymple et al.’s (1998) analysis of interpretive variability
in reciprocals).
Although we will end up adopting a version of this proposal to explain the fact that verbs like those in (5) have default telic interpretations, it is not enough to save Abusch’s analysis from a more serious second problem: there are DAs which appear to have only atelic interpretations. For example, (6a–b) show that DAs derived from the dimensional adjectives wide and deep accept only durative temporal modifiers:
In addition, entailment from the progressive to the perfect is automatic, as shown by the fact that (7a–b), unlike e.g. (8a–b), are contradictory.
These facts are unexpected if a DA such as widen is ambiguous between the two meanings in (9), comparable to those for cool in (4).
In particular, if (9a) were an option, then widen should have a telic interpretation equivalent to become wide, namely “come to have a width that is at least as great as the minimum width that counts as wide in the context of utterance.”5 It would then be possible to simultaneously assert that something widens in the sense of (9b) while denying that it widens in the sense of (9a) (this is Zwicky and Sadock’s (1975) “test of contradiction”), since an object can increase in width without becoming wide. But this is not the case: if it were, then the examples in (7) would fail to generate a contradiction. That is, there would be an interpretation of, for example, (7a) in which the occurrence of widen in the perfective form is understood to mean the same as become wide, not become wider, in which case there would be no incompatibility with the progressive assertion: a gap could be increasing in width without having become wide (see note 5). We can therefore conclude that DAs like widen and deepen resist interpretations parallel to (9a), a fact that deserves explanation.6
A final problem with Abusch’s analysis involves the interpretation of measure phrases in DAs. Consider the following examples:
The measure phrases in these examples specify the amount that the respective subjects change in temperature and width as a result of participating in the event described by the verbs, and in doing so, render the predicates telic (a point to which we will return below). However, it is difficult to see how this result can be achieved given the options in (4) and (9). It might seem reasonable to modify the account so that the measure phrase and adjectival base together provide the value of the inchoative predicate, but this would predict that (10a–b) should have the meanings in (11a–b).
This prediction is obviously incorrect: cool is a gradable adjective that does not combine with measure phrases (see Schwarzschild 2005 and Svenonius and Kennedy 2006 for recent discussion of this issue), and (11b) does not accurately convey the meaning of (10b). Instead, (10a–b) are more accurately paraphrased by (12a–b).
These paraphrases show that measure phrases in DAs express “differential” amounts, just like measure phrases in comparatives: instead of specifying the total amount to which an object possesses some measurable gradable property (as in (11b), where six inches is used to describe the total/maximal width of the gap), such measure phrases convey the extent to which two objects (or the same object at different times) differ along some gradable continuum. An analysis of variable telicity in DAs that is based strictly on the vagueness of the positive form, such as Abusch’s, is not equipped to convey this kind of meaning. (See von Stechow 1984 for a discussion of the problem differential measure phrases present for a semantics of comparatives based on the analysis of vagueness in Kamp 1975 and Klein 1980, on which Abusch builds her analysis of DAs.)
1 We will focus primarily on inchoative forms of DAs in this chapter, even though most have causative variants as well, as it is the semantics of the “inchoative cor” that is crucial to capturing variable telicity. That is, telicity does not correlate with causativity: if a DA shows variable telicity at all, then it shows it in both its causative and inchoative forms (Hay et al. 1999). Since for deadjectival verbs the semantics of the latter are part of the former (on standard assumptions about causative/inchoative alternations; though see Koontz-Garboden 2007), it must be the case that it is the latter on which telicity is based.
2 Abusch does not assume an event semantics; (3b) simply restates the interval-based semantics for become that she assumes (based on Dowty 1979) in terms of an event argument; cf. Krifka (1998b); Parsons (1990).
3 Abusch’s analysis of the atelic interpretation is often characterized as involving a “comparative” semantics, and we will continue to use this label here, but with caution: this characterization is not quite accurate. Abusch’s semantics is similar to e.g. Klein’s (1980) analysis of comparatives in that it involves existential quantification over contextual interpretations of vague predicates, but it is crucially different in not introducing an explicit standard of comparison (the expression contributed by the than constituent in an English comparative construction).
4 Kearns points out that this effect is gradient, with some verbs (like darken) showing it mildly and others (like empty) showing it quite strongly. However, even verbs like empty can take on atelic interpretations when the context is rich enough or other components of the sentence force such readings, as in the case of post-verbal modification by quickly (Kearns 2007):
The sink emptied quickly (but we closed the drain before it became empty).
5 Even if the exact value of such a width is vague or unknown (or unknowable; see Williamson 1992, 1994), it remains the case that (9a) should be semantically telic, since it imposes exactly the same kind of requirement on an event that a DA like cool does in its telic sense in (4a). This is confirmed by the absence of an entailment from the progressive to the perfect for become wide, as shown by (i).
(i) The gap is becoming wide(r), but it hasn’t become wide.
Modification of become wide with an in-PP is not particularly felicitous, but this is presumably due to the vagueness of wide, and therefore not indicative of atelicity.
6 While this conclusion is justified based on the clear contrast between the examples in (7) and those in (8), we suspect that it may be possible under special circumstances and with strong contextual support to understand DAs like widen in a telic, “positive” sense comparable to (9a).